
A statue of René Descartes in Den Haag, Netherlands. I once sat below it, eating a lunch of Patatje Joppie (fries with Joppiesaus) and pickled herring.
Descarte’s chief importance to us now lies in his mental attitude, and his approach to solving problems. He did not always come to conclusions that I can accept, and sometimes did not live up to his own methods, but the significant thing is that he tried to look at the world in a way that would be familiar to a scientist in our time, or to any scholar, lawyer, doctor, or technician trying to maintain an objective, rational discipline.
Formally, the Meditations are written in the “dialectic” style that was the heritage of medieval and renaissance philosophy. But Descartes was not interested in the medieval technique of comparing authorities and making an “argument”. He was more interested in the questions: “What can I claim to know?” “How shall I distinguish between what I believe, and what I can claim as proven?”
Every scientist and lawyer is now familiar with the importance of these questions. I can step outside and see a man robbing another man at gunpoint. After the event, I can give testimony to this, but other people need not believe me if I cannot corroborate it. I myself might not be certain, for instance, that it was not a vivid dream, which I mistook for experience. A chemist might see a significant reaction in a test-tube. Yet, he expects other scientists to suspend judgment on his report until it can be duplicated. The phrasing of his report will be carefully thought out to reflect the epistemological and judicial considerations that science depends on. There are hints and premonitions of this attitude in earlier thinkers, like Aristotle, Euclid, Ibn Sinna, and Aquinas, but it is Descartes who brings them to the forefront, and concentrates on them.
In the Meditations , Descartes works from the premise that he shouldn’t claim anything as true unless he is certain that is true. In other words, he works in a procedure that assumes the falsehood of a statement until it is proven. He recognizes that mind is habituated to “jump to conclusions”, to accept the evidence of the senses automatically. He considers the possibility that the senses might lie, and meditates on the nature of dreams, and the possibility of demonic influence [by which he seems to mean what we would call insanity]. Descartes concludes that dreams, hallucinations and demonic influence can be distinguished from falsehood by their lack of “clearness and consistency” [“lumière et de distinction” [ Méditation seconde , para.10]. He asserts that, if we accept the premise that we are thinking the thought in question, and thus must exist [“ …j’ai reconnu que j’étais, et je cherche quel je suis, moi que j’ai reconnu être. ” Méditation seconde , para.7] , then we have a beginning point (knowledge of existence) and a process (reasoning from the consistency or inconsistency of the evidence of the senses) for making judgements and assertions about the world.
However, while Descartes’ methodology strikes us as “modern”, the subjects which he wishes to apply them to do not. His primary concern is with using these rational techniques to form opinions concerning the existence of God, nature of mind and soul, and other spiritual issues. These issues still occupy many people, but they are not within the purview of the scientific disciplines that Descartes inspired. Appealing to the clearness and distinctness” notion, Descartes sees the existence of God as contingent on one’s knowledge of one’s existence and identity. Exactly how this is so, is not made very clear. He appears to be saying that God must exist because he is imagined, and nothing can be imagined unless there is somehow a referent which exists, albeit it could be a composite of such referents. He does not address the issue that “God” in almost everyone’s conception incorporates inconsistencies and contradictions [e.g. omnipotence and all knowingness, transcending time and space, etc. In the words of Homer Simpson, “Can God create a burrito that is too hot for himself to eat?”] and thus would not pass his own test of “clearness and consistency”.
Meditation VI is concerned with the relationship between the mind and the world outside the self. Having accepted the existence of both himself and of God, he wants to know if he can prove the existence of objects aside from these two. He considers both material objects suggested by the senses and abstractions, such as mathematics, which are experienced within the mind. Given the existence of God, and of himself, he finds it self-evident that God has the power to create a mind existing independent of a body, and to create material objects outside of, and distinct from, both his mind and his body. The question remains, can he assert that this is in fact the case, without violating his methodology of asserting only the provable. Much of this meditation is devoted to the initial step of describing the nature of imagination. He describes the imagining of a three-sided figure (a triangle) as an act of imagination, then compares it to the imagining of a “chiliogon” — a thousand-sided figure. The first he classifies as “imagination”, because it creates an actual image in the mind, and the second as “pure intellect” [“l’intellection ou conception pure ”]. At this stage, he gives no proof that external objects exist, but only asserts that these processes of imagination and intellect, and the distinction between them, make sense only if there is a world of objects to apply them to.
It is here that Descartes appeals to the senses, which, in the earlier Meditations, he has cast doubt on as being able to provide convincing proof. Given that God exists, that he himself exists, and that he has mental processes that can imagine and conceive of material objects with consistency, then there can be only two possibilities. Either the objects suggested by the senses and conceived by imagination actually exist, or God is a liar, or con-man, [“trompeur ”] who is creating a huge fabric of delusion. Descartes flatly asserts that God can not be a liar, and therefore, considers it proven that material objects exist in a consistent, real world.
After considering the implications of a number of deviations from consistency — dreams, hallucinations and the curious phenomenon of “phantom limbs” [where an amputee feels the existence of a limb that is missing], he comes to the conclusion that all fit into a “real” world of which perception and sensory experience are not perfect representations, but which cannot be a total delusion without questioning the moral credentials of God.
Descartes view of the world attempted to build up a logical structure based on simple premises that would allow the mind to explore the world without constantly depending on the arbitrary and miraculous. In this, he was a precursor of the methods of science, and his attitude inspired what would later come to be known as “The Age of Reason”. Cartesian thinking led to astonishing progress in mathematics and science.
However, in the Sixth Meditation, Descartes’ reasoning does not live up to the intent or promise behind the entire treatise. Descartes does not seem to recognize that his statement that “Dieu n’étant point trompeur [para.10]”, that God cannot deceive, is every bit as much an irreducible premise as the initial step “I think, therefore I Am”. One can actually imagine, with total consistency, a universe that consists of God and Descartes’ mind alone, in which God (capable, after all, of anything) has created a complete illusion of material existence. It is within the rules that Descartes has set up for himself.
I would conclude that, while Descartes has created a fascinating structure, and anyone with an inclination to scientific reasoning would approach it with warm feelings and respect, the Méditations fail to accomplish their purpose. Descartes did not create a firm structure of proven physical realism based entirely on the identity of the thinker and the premise of God’s existence.
0 Comments.